International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
Origin and Development of Indian Logic and
Buddhist Logic
Ven.Dr. LenagalaSiriniwasa Thero
Head, Department of Sanskrit, Buddhist and Pali University of Sri Lanka - Homagama, Sri Lanka
1. The Development of Indian Logic
It is very difficult to give satisfactory chronological accounts
of the rise and growth of Indian Logic for the reason that the
texts, which the science of logic or various logical terms
have been mentioned or used, have so far failed to be dated
with certainly. The earliest reference to logic or science of
debate seem to be contained in chāndogyaupanisad where
Nārada includes among the disciplines studied by him, one
called vākovakyam(Ch.U.7.1.2).The term is explained by
Sankarācārya as meaning logic(tarkasāstra),but it seems to
signify the art or science of debate. Among later works the
arthasāstra of Kautilya (400 B.C.) mentions logic under the
name of anvīksikī, which is the first among the four
disciplines, alluded to by him (arthsāstra 1-2.p.6). Perhaps
even in those days, as now, the followers of reason or logic
were not very orthodox people. Arthasāstra says that a
person well versed in the art of governing ought to know
logic also. Next important references are to be met with in
the kathāvatthu (300 B.C.), which is a part of the
abhidharmapiµaka in Buddhism. The work mentions
Anuyoga(inquiry),âharana(illustration), patina (proposition)
[1]. In the Mahābhāratanot only the term Upanayana
(application of reason), Niggaha(Nigraha-humilation of or
defeat),Anvīksikī,etc. have been used, but also there is a
reference to the five member sentence or speech whose
strong and weak points were thoroughly known to Nārada
[2] In vanaparva,a chapter of Mahābhārata there is a story
about the controversy between vandi, the court philosopher
of king Janaka, and Astāvākra, a young scholar. The story is
illustrative of the fact that the rules of controversy were
known at the time of Mahābhārata. It is certainly true that
rules of controversy cannot be identified with the theory of
logic. But it is the rules of controversy, which are primarily
discussed in aphorisms of Aksapāda. So the reference to the
rules of controversy in Mahābhārata is very important for
the historical development of logic.
The Mahābhārata relates the story of a Brāhmaõa who on
account of his being addicted to logic chopping all through
his life was born a jackal in his next birth. [3] According to
Vyāsa, spiritual doctrines cannot be communicated to those
made callous by dialectics (tarkasāstradagdhāya). [4]
Manu-samhita, though recommending Anvīksī(logic) as a
useful and necessary study for a king and insisting on a
hetuka and a tarkin being indispensable members of a legal
assembly, [5] enjoins excommunication upon those
dvijas(twice-born class) who have become skeptics (nāstika)
owing to recourse to hetusāstra and set at defiance sruti and
smruti, the two recognized sources of religion. [6] Manu
urges that dharma is to be analyzed by means of
argumentation in conformity with the Vedas. [7] Though
there are several references to the necessity and usefulness
of logic as well as debates and discussions, nowhere in
Brāhmanic literature is logic appraised at its full value. On
the contrary, its importance has been emphasized, if at all, to
prove things in concurrence with the beliefs and doctrines of
the Vedas whose authority was commonly acknowledged to
be one of the several means of right cognition (āgama or
sabdapramāna) in the Brāhmanical schools of philosophy.
[8] As the Vedas present no set philosophy, the Upanisads
likewise are diffuse and figurative in their expressions. It is
for this reason that the Upanisads to which the germs of all
later philosophical thoughts can be definitely traced have
little to say about logical problems. [9] But the debates and
the discussions found in the Upanisads may be regarded as
the anticipations of the logical system that followed.
Upanisads, though they encourage debates and discussions,
declare that truths regarding Brahman are not obtainable by
argumentation alone (naisātarkenamatirāpane). [10] It is
also to be noted in this connection that an approach to
religion or metaphysics purely from the standpoint of
reason, quite irrespective of the conclusion that may follow,
is not much favoured in Brāhmanicliterature in general. In
Manusmruti there is a reference to tarkaor logic and it is
asserted that those who follow tarka would not attain Svarga
or heaven.
The most important fact about these all documents of logic
is that they mention ten parts or Avayavās of syllogism
instead of traditional five. Some of the Jain logicians like
Bāhubali, also refer to these ten parts. These additional five
parts of the syllogism are strictly irrelevant to the theory of
syllogism and so Vātsyāyana, the commentator of Aksapāda
Sutras rejects them. But certainly these additional five parts
give rise to much speculation.
The story of Indian logic covers a period of over two
thousand years. From the time of Mahābhārata, when logic
was still a practical art of controversy, logical theory has
steadily and constantly developed in India till about the
seventeenth century A.D., when it culminated in a formal
discipline of language in the neo-logical school of
Navadeepa in Bengal. All this time it is spread through three
different disciplines, the discipline of orthodox Hindu logic,
the discipline of Buddhist logic and the discipline of Jain
logic. Each of these schools produced many logicians of
great eminence who attacked and counter-attacked the
logicians of the other schools by trying to point out the
weakness in the theory of the opponents. Thus, for example,
Nāgarjuna,Dinnāga and Dharmakīrti tried to attack the
Hindu logicians by pointing out the dimensions of Hetu(or
reason)and its significance in the theory of inference. On the
other hand the Hindu logicians tried to uproot the Apoha
theory of negation, [11] which was accepted by Buddhist
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
890
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
logicians. The result was that logical theory became richer
and richer and culminated in the finest and subtlest
instrument of human thought and reasoning. Philosophers of
the other schools of orthodox Hindu thought also contributed
to the growth of logic though they rejected the metaphysical
tenets, they accepted the general methodology of Nyāya-
Vaisesika school and soon thanks to their efforts it instead of
remaining a mere school of philosophy, attained a position
of pre-eminence in the science of methodology. Thus in
ancient India a pupil was required to learn first grammar and
then Nyāya or logic. Unless a student took lessons in Nyāya
he was not supposed to be competent to study
purvaMimāmsa or Vedānta.
2. The Meaning of the Term Nyāya
The earliest attempt to define Nyāya seems to have been
made by vātsyāyana in his Bhāsyaon the Nyāyasutra.
According to him it is the examination of objects by mean of
pramānas. The definition seems to be wide, including as it
does the ontological topics as presented in Nyāyasutra. Later
on, particularly in the hands of the Buddhist logicians,
Nyāya or logic became identified with the discussion of the
pramānas. This seems to be the most general and current
meaning of the term Nyāya in Indian philosophy. The
carakasamhita contains for the first time an exposition of
the doctrine of syllogism under the name of sthāpana. Hence
it is presumed that the word Nyāya as an equivalent for logic
came into use about the composition of that samhita that is,
about the opening of the Christian era. The only systematic
treatment of the Nyāya can be found in the Nyāyasåtra of
Gautama in later lines (Nyāyasåtra of Gautama-2
nd
century
A.D./Uddyotakara-about 635 A.D./Vācaspati Mishra-about
841 A.D.).
The literature of Buddhism gives little aid; the Buddhist
doctrine of perception in its developed form has affinity with
the Nyāya, but no derivation suggests itself; either follows a
line of thought already foreshadowed in the Upanisads. [13]
The old pāli texts ignore the names Nyāya or vaisesika: in
the Brahmajālasuttawe hear in lieu of them only of takki,
‘Sophist’ and vīman ‘casuist’ and in the Udānatakkikās
appear as in the epic and Puranas.The silence is of
importance, still more so the fact that in the
Kathāvatthuppakarana,which does not claim to a greater
antiquity than Asoka’s alleged council about 255 B.C., we
find no reference to either school, and nothing more
significant than use of the terms patiñña, ‘proposition’,
upanaya, ‘application of a reason’, and niggaha,
‘humiliation’, which later in Gautama's logic are technical
terms, but which at this period have their more general
sense. It is in keeping with this that the Nyāya, under the
name nīti and the vaisesika, first appear in the milindapañha.
3. The Classical Nyāya School
Founded by Gautama Aksapāda probably at second century
A.D., the school, like its ally Vaisesika, represents the most
stubborn proponent of realism in Indian philosophical
tradition. Scholars have divergent opinions regarding the
authorship of Nyāyasāstra. Some of them, for instance,
Dr.Vidyabhusana, maintain that Gautama and Aksapāda
were two different persons. Out of the five subjects
discussed in the Nyāyasåtra, viz, (1) pramāna (2) prameya
(3) vāda (4) avayava and (5) anyamataparīksa, the first,
second and third, which constituted Anviksikī, were
compiled by Gautama and the last two were introduced by
Aksapāda. “Aaksapāda”, according to Dr. Vidyābhusana,
was, therefore, the real author of the Nyāyasutra, which
derived a considerable part of its materials from the
Anvīksikīvidya of Gautama. Just as Caraka was the redactor
of the Agnivesatantra or the Ayurveda, Aksapāda was the
redactor of the Anvīksikī of Gautama. Vātsyāyana, the
author of the earliest extant commentary on the Nyāyas³tra
vaguely refers to some other commentators and gives
different explanations of some terms or concepts, but their
works are no longer available. It seems that there must have
been a gap of at least two hundred years between Aksapāda
and vātsyāyana.
Later Naiyayikās like Uddyotakara, Jayanta and vācaspati
engaged themselves in explaining various theses put forth in
Gautama’sNyāyasåtra, the fundamental text of the school,
and vehemently defended them against, above all, their arch-
rival, and the Buddhist non-realist.
Nyāya is mainly a logical and epistemological, and its
metaphysics is mostly subordinate to or overshadowed by
the Vaisesika metaphysical theory of category
(padartha).So, as a common practice, we take the latter to
bear the name “Nyāyavaisesika”. The Nyāyavaisesika word
is populated with real (sat), particular existents, including
substances, quality-particulars, then, universals,
particularities, the relation of inherence, and finally absence.
The metaphysics is thing-oriented, with substance forming
the central and the most essential category. Substances are
the substrata of qualities, action and universals, etc. which
inhere in them. They are either non-composite, like earth-
atoms, sky and selves, or composite, composed of
indivisible, eternal atoms of the four elemental substances,
earth, water, fire and air.
Nyāya accepts four types of means of knowing, viz.
perception, inference, analogy and word-generated
cognition. Unlike the Buddhist, the school draws a
distinction between a mean of knowledge and the resulting
knowledge. In any case a knowledge-episode (pramā) is and
object-accordant (yathārtha) presentative cognition.
A cognition or awareness is a transitory quality of the self.
Naiyāyikās denounce the thesis of self-awareness. For them
an awareness-episode, unless it is pre-predicative, can be
known by a reflective awareness called ‘anuvyavasāya’.
Now, according to Nyāya, a sense-awareness of an object is
void of a concrete form, yet its reflection perceives not only
the awareness itself but also the object. This problem is thus
resolved: by dint of the first order awareness setting up,
ānalaksana-wise, an epistemic relation the reflective
awareness comes to perceive even the object of the first
order awareness.
For Nyāya there is no intentional content, e.g., concepts, that
mediates between awareness and its external object-
complex. The content of awareness is indeed its external
object. For the Buddhist a conceptual awareness may
ascertain as the same various different homogeneous objects.
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
891
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
Projecting a conceptual-intentional form onto the objects
does this. And different ascertaining awareness may have a
very similar intentional form. But Jayanta (NyāyaMañjari
11: 26-27) repudiates the view as he argues that if the
seemingly generic form revealed by the conceptual
awareness is distinct from the awareness, then it is just a real
phase of the latter, the form is as specific and
instant(ksanika) as the awareness.
“The Nyāya system of philosophy is generally identified
with logic. But it is by no means true that it is a system of
logic alone and nothing else. It is primarily a method of
controversy” [14] Logic, like Metaphysics, is only a part of
it. It is a matter of history that adherents of the Nyāya
system of philosophy laid great stress on methodology,
which, in the course of time, was also accepted in large
measure by other systems of philosophy to prove their
propositions. Though it does prameya and apavarga
amongst the categories, from the aphorisms, which have
come down to us the metaphysical presuppositions of the
system, are by no means clear. On the other hand it is clear
that the system provides instruments of controversy and
decision. But traditionally and in its later thought at least, the
followers of the Nyāya system accepted the metaphysics of
the Vaisesikās.In fact later Indian logic is mostly the
development of vaisesika logic, unifying it with the main
tenets of the Nyāya, In fact, even Udyotakara regards
kanāda, the profounder of Vaisesika system as a great sage
and adores him with even greater veneration than Gautama.
The author of the vaisesika system was kanāda. His other
name seems to be Uluka. Etymologically ‘kanāda’ means
one who eats atoms. Kanāda was, perhaps, so called because
he believed that the world was composed of atoms. Like the
Greek Democrats, he tried to reduce everything to four kinds
of atoms, the atom of fire, the atom of earth, the atom of air
and the atom of water.
The logics of the Vaisesikas and the Naiyāyikas proceeded
for some time on parallel lines, but were ultimately unified
in the neo-logical school. Perhaps the works of Udayana
who wrote on both the systems must have been partly
responsible for this unification. In fact some as the founder
of neo-logical school has regarded Udayana. He wrote
profusely and criticized almost every logical doctrine of the
Buddhists. The systematization of the logical doctrines of
Indian origin is most probably due to Udayana.
Udayana seems to have flourished in the 10
th
century A.D.
Most probably he belonged to the Saiva school of religious
sect. One of his celebrated works, known as Kusumāñjali-‘A
bunch of flowers-is a work devoted to establishing the
existence of God. In this work, as in others, he discusses in
detail, the whole theory of logic and the work is indeed very
important from the point of logical theory.
He wrote a commentary called Kiranāvali-‘A beam of rays’-
on the Bhāsya of Praœastapāda and on Nyāya side wrote
another commentary called Nyāya- vārtikatātparya-
parisuddhi on Nyāya- rtika- tātparya of vācaspati Mishra.
Another important work of his is Atmavādaviveka where he
tries to prove the existence of soul and analyses its nature. It
is here that he discusses the Buddhist doctrines of Apoha and
ksanabhanga or flux. He revived and re-established the
Nyāya and Vaisesika theory. On account of his epoch-
making work, the TatvaCintamaniGangesaUpadhyaya is
usually called the father of neo-logical school. Udayana was,
at least, responsible for preparing the ground for that great
work of Gangesa.
Before Udayana, there flourished great logicians like
Vātsyāyana, Udyotakara, Vācaspati Mishra, Bhāsarvajña,
Jayanta and several others on the Nyāya side. On the
Vaisesika side there were celebrated authors like
Prasastapāda, Sridhara and Vyomasiva. The work of
Prasastapāda is known as Padartha-Dharma-samgraha. It is
usually known as Bhāsya though an independent work
running along the line of Vaisesika Sutra. It is very valuable
because it is the earliest Vaisesikawork available. Unlike the
NyāyaSutra which has been arranged by Vācaspati,
Vaisesika Sutras are not properly arranged and the
authenticity of many of them is doubted.
Another important work on the Vaisesika side is the Nyāya-
kandali of Sridhara. It is a commentary on
PrasastapādaBhāsya and shows a great advance in logical
theory. Another very early commentary on the Bhāsya of
prasatapāda is known as Vyomavati and is useful as it
preserves many of the doctrines of Indian logic in its early
form. When the new system of education was introduced in
India, the study of Indian logic was neglected; the
development of logic came to an end.
4. The Buddhist School
The Buddhist epistemological school is virtually founded by
Dinnāga, a Yogācāra philosopher, at the early sixth century
A.D. As Dinnāga and his successors also subscribed
themselves to or made use of certain views of the Buddhist
Sautrantika School, the school is also known as Sautrantika-
Yogācāra school. Dharmakīrti later took up Dinnāga’s
theses, enlarged and refined them against criticisms from the
rival schools. Dharmakīrti wrote a number of books
explaining his viewpoints on perception, inference, language
and relation, etc. Apart from Dinnāga and Dharmakīrti, we
can refer to Sāntaraksita and his pupil Kamalasīla,
especially, their new semantic theory. Although Yogācāra
metaphysicians are idealists, the Buddhist epistemologists
normally accept the existence of mind-independent reality. It
is well known that in NyāyabinduDharmakīrti says to the
effect that a particular (svalaksana) gives rise to different
immanent objective appearances according to it is near to or
remote from the perceiver.
Buddhist literature generally falls into two divisions, Pāli
and Sanskrit. In Pāli Buddhist literature there is not a single
treatise devoted to logic; nevertheless it gives very clear
indications of current logical doctrines. As Keith figures in
the Pāli literature, Buddha is ‘a reasoner whose interlocutors
are not his match; his weapons against them, beside his
authority are analogy, simile, parable and an occasional trace
of inductions by simple enumerations of cases’. [15] We
must also bear in mind in this connection that in the
personality of Buddha the preacher and the philosopher
blended together. While Buddha gave a rationalistic
philosophy in an age of Upanisadic dogmatism, he had to
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
892
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
deal with ‘relatively immature minds’, ‘the man in the street’
and 'the average bhikkhu or sekha (learner in the order). ‘But
any way the prevailing method of the Buddha in his replies
to interlocutors is one of gentle 'reasonableness’. [16]
The period of Pāli Buddhism was rather one of criticism
than of construction and it is not a matter of surprise that we
do not find during this period any systematic study of logical
principles. In the later period of Sanskrit Buddhism when the
schism of the Buddhist institute resulted in the four principle
schools of Mādhyamika, Yogācāra, Sautrantika and
Vaibhāsika, every school for the purpose of opposing rival
doctrines as well as vindicating its own, found it necessary
to evolve logical methods of arguments and thus gradually
there grew up a vast literature on logic which to our great
misfortune, is now a mere catalogue of names. Excepting
only a few, almost all the treatises on Buddhist logic are lost.
But some have providentially escaped utter destruction as
they were translated into Tibetan or Chinese. The Japanese
scholar SadajiroSugiura has given an account of the
Buddhist logic in Chinese and Japanese in his work, ‘Hindu
logic as preserved in China and Japan’ (1900).Dr.Satis
Chandra Vidyābhusana’s monumental work-History of
Indian Logic, (1921), presents an elaborate account of the
Buddhist Nyāya literature which was transported to Tibet
and remains up till now, buried in its Tibetan translation.
Dharmakīrti’sNyāyabindu with the Nyāyabindutīka is the
only complete and comprehensive work on Buddhist logic
that has survived in its original Sanskrit form. The six
Buddhist Nyāya tracts (Bib. Indica) edited by
MahāmahopādhyayaDr.H.P. æastri discusses some
interesting problems of logic. The Tattvasamgraha of
Sāntaraksita with Pañjikā of Kamala sīla (Gaekwad Oriental
Series), an encyclopaedic Buddhist work, gives a
comprehensive account of Buddhist logic. The
Nyāyapravesa, Part І (Sanskrit text) and Part ІІ (Tibetan
text) in the above series in an important manual of the
Dinnāga’s school of logic. The pre-Dinnāga Buddhist texts
on logic from Chinese Sources by Professor Tucci in the
same series have no doubt been a very valuable publication.
The publication of a few more works on Buddhist logic has,
however, been announced in the Gaekwad Oriental Series.
But that we possess of the Buddhist Nyāya literature is
insignificant in comparison with what has perished of it.
It is much to be regretted that Buddhist logic has in recent
times scarcely received any attention of the orthodox Indian
Scholars of logic (Nyāya) who are occupied with the
subtleties of the new school of Indian logic (Navya-Nyāya).
But it is worth noting that Buddhist logic has had greater
influence upon Navya-Nyāya than the ancient Brāhmanic
logic. While Gautama introduces sixteen categories
(padartha), rather topics of discussion in his logical system
(i.e. the Nyāyasutra) the Buddhist logicians were restricted
to one topic only, viz.pramāna. The Navya-Naiyayikas also
exclusively confined themselves to pramā and discussion
pertinent to it in their extensive and elaborate speculations in
the field of logic. Gautama's Nyāyasutra has no reference to
vyāpti or the invariable concomitance between the
probandum and the probans, which is the pivot of inferential
argument, though Vātsyāyana’s suggestive remarks in his
commentary on the Nyāyasutra 1.1.39 are worth noting. All
the subtle discussions on the invariable concomitance or
vyāptithat have found a prominent place in the NavyaNyāya
have, it appears, been profoundly influenced by the theories
of inference as held by Dinnāga and Dharmakīrti.
It is to be noted in this connection that the erudite
Brāhmanic scholars like Uddyotakara, Vācaspati, Udayana
and Partahasarati Mishra appear to have possessed a
profound knowledge of Buddhist logic, which they exhibit
in course of their criticism of the Buddhist doctrines.
The Jaina philosophers also took interest in Buddhist logic.
Not only did they refer to the Buddhist views in their own
works by way of criticism but they also sometimes wrote
commentaries on the Buddhist logical treatises, e.g.
Haribhadra’sNyāyapravesapañjikāon the Nyāyapravesa and
Mallavādin'sDharmottaratippanaka (Bib.Buddhica) on the
Nyāyabindutīka of Dharmottara. It deserves to be mentioned
here that these commentaries along with the texts,
Nyāyapravesa, Nyāyabindutīka(with Nyāyabindu) and a few
more texts of Buddhist logic that have survived in their
original Sanskrit form.
The Nyāyasutra of Aksapāda and the Bhāsya of Vātsyāyana
show the influence of Buddhist critics like Nāgarjuna and
refute some of their charges. Dinnāga then sets himself to
criticizing Brāhmanic doctrines as those of Aksapāda and
Vātsyāyana .To answer the objections of Dinnāga, urged
against Aksapāda and Vātsyāyana,Uddyotakara made an
attempt to interpret elaborately the Nyāyasutra of Aksapada
and the Bhāsyaof Vātsyāyana with all their implications.
And again as Buddhist criticisms on Aksapāda and
Vātsyāyana led Uddyotakara to write his Nyāyavārtika,
Brahmanic criticism on Dinnāga similarly induced
Dharmakīrti to write the Pramānavārtika, a metrical
commentary upon the Pramānasamuccaya effecting all
possible improvements in their own defense. Dharmakīrti
was again answered by Vācaspati, the great Brāhmaic
Philosopher and commentator. Dharmakīrti was succeeded
by a number of Buddhist logicians like Devendrabodhi,
Vinītadeva, Jinendrabodhi, Santaraksita, Dharmottara,
Arcata and jetari, many of whom wrote commentaries and
sub-commentaries on the treatises of Dinnāga and
Dharmakīrti and occasionally criticized Brāhmanic writers
like Kumarila and Vācaspati. But they did not possess much
originality of thinking like the two masters: Dinnāga and
Dharmakīrti. Owing to these mutual conflict and opposition
Indian logic had the opportunity of developing by a process
of alternate criticism and construction.
“The continuity of Buddhist logic came up to about 1000
A.D. when the decline and fall of Buddhism in India
sounded its death-knell. During this time with the revival of
Brahmanism Brāhmanic logic being tinctured with Buddhist
influence came to be studied over again and thus was laid
the foundation of the new school of Brahmanic
logic(NavyaNyāya) which flourished later on so luxuriantly
in Mithila and Nadia”. [17]
The history of logic in India presents three stages: The first
stage, when dogmatic philosophy and authority reigned
supreme and was thrown into the back-ground; the second
stage, characterized by a rampant revolt against authority
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
893
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
when logic was raised to the rank of philosophy and was on
a par with it; and the third stage, when logic got the upper
hand over philosophy and in a sense smothered it, but at last
lost its self in its own groove. Buddhist logic, it is to be
noted, belongs to the second stage.
Classical Indian epistemologists concerned themselves with
examinations of various means of knowing (pramāna)
regarding their number, functioning, object, validity, etc.
The Buddhist accepts only two means of knowing, viz.,
perception and inference. It is often said that Dinnāga
reduces verbal cognition to inference. In
Pramānasamuccaya he does say that the cognition from the
utterance of the worthy person is inferential, for it and
inference similar in being non-deceiving. The two are also
alike in being conceptual and having a negative route to
reality. Yet, to affirm these similarities (and for under
inference) is not necessarily to reduce verbal Cognition to
inference. It may be the case that Dinnāga just found a
common basis for both of them.
Dharmakīrti characterizes both perception and inference as a
correct (samyak) knowing in the sense of being non-
deceiving (avisamvādi) in its adherence to efficient
operation or to the fulfillment of useful effect (arthakriya). It
is held in Pramānavārtika11 6d-7a that the own form of a
cognition is known through the practical activity of
confirmation regarding the production of the intended effect.
Dharmakīrti account of the notion of Pramāna in relation to
its validity is pragmatic. Pramāna- vārtika- vrutti
(Manorathanandin in pandeya-1989) however, suggests that
when illusion, doubt and apprehension are absent, the
validity of awareness is known intrinsically. [18]
The notion of non-deceiving does not define a correspondent
relation with one relatum, the cognition, to represent the
other, the intended object. As said, the notion means
adherence to efficient operation. So, we need to see whether
there is any discordance between what the cognition takes its
object to be and the production of the concerned effect. One
sees something as water from a fair distance but, when
approaching it, finds no water there. Then, the first seeing-
experience turns out to be deceiving; it disappoints or
dissatisfies (visamvādin) the confirming experience.
On the other hand, the Buddhist views conceptual cognition
as erroneous, for it apprehends the real through an unreal
conceptual veil. [19] Thus, the immanent appearance of such
cognition fails to conform to the form of the external object:
it fails to present its object the way it is with its failure of
conformance (arthasārupya) or its miss-presentation; a
conceptual cognition can be both pragmatically non-
deceiving and presentatively erroneous.
5. The Epistemological Outlook in Early
Buddhism
Early Buddhism is primarily concerned with practical
problems of life. Its aim is to attain supreme perfections
through proper conduct. To attain this aim knowledge of
truth and reality is necessary. Thus the problem of
knowledge forms the basis for ethics and metaphysics in
early Buddhism.
In AnguttaraNikāya, we find the division of knowledge into
six kinds. [20] This is just a division of knowledge and has a
little to do with the theory of knowledge.
The Buddha distinguishes between paranormal and sensory
or intellectual knowledge and attack greater value to the
former one by saying that it in “Profound, difficult to see
and comprehend, serene, excellent super-rational, subtle and
comprehensive only by the wise”. [21]
The highest knowledge [22] too, according to early
Buddhists, is conceived by extra-ordinary visual perceptions,
through the eye of wisdom. One is to know and see truth
directly. It is interesting to see the significance of the use of
'knowing' and ‘seeing’ in Buddhism-The Buddha uses the
word 'seeing' along with 'knowing' in many contexts. [23]
To both normal and paranormal perception Buddhism offers
empirical explanations.
Inference (anumāna) in Indian thought necessarily both
inductive and deductive process. While seeking for material
truth corresponding to reality, mere formal truth would not
serve. Probably this is the reason why tarka (Pali -takka),
which is the method showing formal consistency, is not
recognized by early Buddhist as an independent source of
knowledge.
Early Buddhism bases its inference both a normal and Para-
normal perception and we find many such references in Pāli
texts. [24] This is the case of inference based on normal
perception with regard to inference drawn on the basis of
paranormal perception also there are many references. We
find the Buddha asking monks to cultivate and practice the
noble eight-fold path and saying ‘whatever a monk
cultivates the noble eight-fold path it leads him to Nibbāna’.
[25] This kind of statements are said to be based on the
direct paranormal perception of the Buddha himself. Many
instances containing inferential passages are found in
AnumānaSutta of Majjhima Nikāya. [26]
There are also references, to fallacies of inference based on
both normal and paranormal perception in the canon.
The Buddha refuses to accept ‘authority’ (sabda) as valid
mean of knowledge. Many scholars are of the opinion that
the Buddha himself has adopted many views from pre-
Buddhist thought. [27]
But the Buddha claims that he has influenced the old ideas
on the basis of his own direct personal experience and not on
the ground of authority. [28] His non-acceptance of
authority as independent from his criticism of six ways of
knowing based on authority. [29] He criticized that all six
theories may be true or false. [30] The Buddha demands that
his own statements should be tested and if found true can be
accepted and if found false can be rejected. This shows that
his attitude to authority is critical and not dogmatic. Saddhā-
faith too, which is an important aspect in teaching of the
Buddha, is not to be confused with uncritical, dogmatic and
blind faith.
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
894
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
6. The Role of Tarka in Early Buddhism
Many scholars have called the Buddha a rationalist in
different senses. But many instances show him not to be in
favour of rational theories, rather we see him criticizing
rationalists (takki) in pāli cannon. Moreover he has
dissociated himself from the class of rationalist (takki) and
traditionalists (anussāvika) and has associated himself with
experiencialists. We find him criticizing the four different
kinds of knowledge based on reason viz. 1.takkahetu,
2.Nayahetu, 3.Ākāra-parivitakkana and 4.ditthi-
nijjhānakkhanti. In all these forms of reasoning their
unreliability is pointed out on the ground that they may be
well or ill reasoned and true or false.
Though reason has not been accepted as a means of valid
knowledge, its limited value is not ignored. [31] It is utilized
to expose the absurdity of the opponents view by pointing
out its inner-inconsistency and indirectly to show the
validity of one's position. [32]
Buddha lays emphasis upon individual experience and not
infrequently he declares in express terms that the path to be
adopted is what one oneself recognizes as true. “Then
monks, what you have just said is only what you yourselves
have recognized, what you yourselves have comprehended,
what you yourselves understood, is it not so?” “It is even so?
Lord”. [33] The Lord Buddha is said to have admonished his
followers on one occasion thus: “Do not accept, oh Bhikkus,
my words out of any respect for me, but accept them for
what they are worth after proper scrutiny, just as a piece of
gold is accepted by an expert after it is put to fire, cut or
tested on the touchstone”. [34] “No sentence”, to quote Mrs.
Rhys David, “occurs oftener than Tam kissahetu? What is
the reason of that?” [35] In PāliTripitaka. This tendency of
Buddhism to appeal to reason and argument accelerated the
development of logic in the hands of the Buddhist
philosophers who took it up with all earnestness for the
purpose of challenging the antagonistic views and
vindicating their own.
7. The Use of ‘Upamā’ in Canon
Comparison (Upamā), though not accepted as a valid means
of Knowledge, has not been ignored as useless. In many
instances parables and similes have been used to make the
views clear to the nearest. A section in MajjhimaNikāya is
called OpammaVagga [36] as it is rich in parables and
similes. The Buddha was well aware of the intellectual
gradation amongst his disciples in the discourse to give clear
meaning of the idea contained in them.
8. The Art of Debate in Kathāvatthu
About hundred years after the passing away of the Buddha
the monks had differences of opinions regarding the actual
sayings and the interpretations of their master. The
dissensions brought, about schism in the Sangha and within
two or three centuries after the Buddha's death as many as
eighteen sects arose. Each of these sects in order to hold
their views firmly started criticizing the views of others. The
resorted to arguments in the form of debate to condemn their
opponents. This is evident from Kathāvatthu which was
compiled during the reign of Asoka in the Third Buddhist
council.
In Kathāvatthu the heretical doctrines were thoroughly
examined and refuted. Its attempt is to reduce the view of
the heterodox schools to absurdity. The discussion
proceeded in the form of question and answer and the
answer of the opponent are often shown to be based on the
contradictory assumptions.
The text opens with the controversial point whether the Soul
(Pudgala) is known in the sense of a real and ultimate fact or
not. Theravādins do not admit the existence of soul
(Pudgala) as an ultimate fact while Pudgalavādins, the
respondents, assert that there is an ultimate reality called
Soul (Pudgala).
They argue:
Theravādins- Is the Soul (Pudgala) known in the sense of a
real ultimate fact (is A=B)?
Pudgalavādins Yes.
Theravādins-Is the Soul (Pudgala) known in the same way
as a real and ultimate fact is known (is C=D)?
Pudgalavādins- No that cannot be said.
Theravādins- Acknowledge your defeat.
If A is B then C should be D. But as C is not D therefore A
should also be not B. Here B is affirmed of A but not D of
C, which is false and so the answer is refuted. This is the
cause of anuloma and in contrast to this indirect method
(patikamma) is used by the Pudgalavādin to prove
Theravādin wrong where in the Theravādin affirms not B of
A but deny not D of C which is wrong according to
Puggalavādins.
When the arguments take place between the two they use
Niggaha (the rejoinder causing defeat of the
opponent).Upanaya (application) Nigamana (conclusion)
etc. to strengthen their arguments. In course of their
arguments they change the place that is to say sometimes the
Theravādin is a respondent and sometimes the Puggalavādin.
The subject matter of the argument also changes with
reference to space, time and things. When a case is presented
through a simple comparison, it is called
Suddhikasamsandana.For example:
Pudgalavādin maintains that A is B and M is B and also say
that A and M are not distinct. To this the Theravādin
answers if we assert separately that A is B and M is B, Then
A and M should be distinct.
A section on Lakkhanayuttikathā deals with the definition of
terms, while another section on Vacanasodhana’deals
with distribution of terms. In the controversy of
vacanasodhana the extension of the subject in relation to its
predicate is set forth. Theradin ask whether all A is B and
all B is A. To this Puggalavādin answers all A is B But some
B areA and some are not. This shows how the early
Buddhists were conversant with the distribution of terms.
Thus we see that the doctrines are put forward in the form of
Questions and answers and systematic logical methods are
applied in this debate of Kathāvatthu. Though not a separate
logical treatises of the later time, many technical terms of
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
895
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
logic found in Nyāya treatise already find mention in
kathāvatthu. B.C. Law has rightly observed that “In
kathāvatthu, we have a great book of controversy which lies
at the immediate background of the entire Nyāya literature”.
[37]
9. The Use of Dilemma in MilindaPañha
Milinda Pañha [38], a beautiful prose wrote has its unique
position in the non- canonical Pāli literature. Apart from
being a comprehensive exposition of Buddhist metaphysics,
ethics and psychology, Milindapañha is the only Pāli work
which an explicit reference to logic called nīti or Nyāya. It
contains questions of king Milinda who was well versed in
logic and the answers of Nāgasena, who seems to surpass
the former in the same, or various topics. The dialogue
between them shows how scholars carried on debates and
arguments in these days.
Fourth book of the text viz. ‘MendakaPañha’ contains many
dilemma put forward by the king for the venerable one to
solve. For instance-Milinda asks Nāgasena to explain why
the Buddha refused to answer certain questions. He added he
must have refrained from answering out of ignorance or out
of wish to conceal something (A is either B or not B). Either
of the disjunctive statements should be true. To this double
pointed dilemma Nāgasena answered in negative saying that
neither of the statement is true (A is neither B nor not B) and
explained that the questions put to the Lord were not to be
answered as there is no reason or object for answering them,
the very nature of those questions was such that they could
not but be put aside.
10. The Nature of Questions in Buddhism
Truth or falsity can be asserted of a proposition only after it
has been tally analyzed. Buddha who claims to be an
analysts, [39] distiguishes between categorical and non-
categorical propositions, while saying, “I have taught and
laid down doctrines which cannot be categorically asserted.”
[40] The four noble truths come under the first group and the
Avyākatavatthuniunder the second. Some of the non-
categorical propositions are analyzable while some others
are non-analyzable. Thus division of statements according to
their truth-value resulted in a division of four types of
questions. There are the four types of questions
(‘cattārimāni……pañhavyakaraõāni’):
1) EkamsaVyākarasa question which are explained
categorically.
2) PatipucchaVyākaranīyo questions which are answered
after a counter-question has been put.
3) VibhajjaVyākaranīyo questions which are explained
analytically and
4) Thapanīyo questions that are set aside. [41]
However in the Pāli canon, apart from this classification of
questions we hardly find any explanation or illustration,
which was later provided in the Abhidharmakoùa. [42] Of
these four types of questions the Thapanīya or the Avyakata
the inexpressible ones find mention in many dialogues of
the canon. Then metaphysical theses are enumerated. [43]
The Mahāsanghikas extended this to fourteen theses by
adding four, logical alternatives to sassatolokoand
antavāloko’ on which the Buddha refused to give any
answer and set them aside. The Buddha thought that none
of the logical alternations could be categorically asserted. So
he preferred keeping silent. This 'silence' of the Buddha later
formed the basis of Mādhyamikas dialectic.
The history of Buddhist thought evinces two types of
following of the Buddha, one philosophical and the other
theological. Theologically, his followers from two camps
known as Hīnayāna and Mahāyāna, each having many sects
and sub sects were spread in the world. Philosophically,
Buddhist thought in India has four broad divisions,
namely,Vaibhāsika, Sautrantika, Madhyamika, and
Yogācāra.NārāyanaBhaµµa in Mānameyodaya cryptically
summarizes the basic thrust of each of these four schools as
follows:
MukhyoMādhyamikovivartamakhilamsunyasyamenejagat
Yogācāra mate tusantimatayahtesāmvivarto'khilam
artho'stiksanikotvasavanumitokathyetiSautrantiko
pratyaksamksanabhanguramcasakalamVaibhasikobhāsate.
That is, the Mādhyamika is the most important philosophical
school, which regards the entire world to be an apparent
manifestation of sunya. The next school is Yogācāra,
according to which ideas alone are real, and the entire world
is an apparent manifestation of ideas. The third school is that
of the Sautrantikas, which maintains that there are objects
existing independently of the ideas, but they are momentary,
and their existence is known only through inference. The last
school is known as Vaibhāsika, which holds that all objects
are momentary and perceivable.
For the sake of easy understanding, these four schools can
be put in a particular logical order as Vaibhāsika,
Sautrantika, Mādhyamika, and Yogācāra. Perhaps this may
also be the chronological order. All these four schools claim
authenticity and faithfulness to Buddha's thought. Buddha
was quite prolific in his ideas, and it may not be difficult to
find rudiments of all these four schools in his thoughts. The
doctrine of impermanence (anityata), which subsequently
was formulated as the doctrine if momentariness
(ksanikavāda), and the doctrine of dependent origination
(pratītyasamutpada) are the common planks for all these
four schools. All the schools believe in the ideas of rebirth
and nirvāna. Their deference is only in terms of the
development of logical structures based on these doctrines
and ideas. I shall briefly discuss the major points of
difference characterizing each of these schools. The school
of Mādhayamika and Yogācāra (Vijñānavāda) are idealistic
in their thrust and are associated with the Mahāyāna
tradition. However, these four schools constitute significant
facets of later Buddhist thought.
Vaibhāsika School
The Vaibhāsika School seems to have acquired this name
because it relies upon a commentary on the Tripitakaknown
as Vibsā. This school upholds dualism of mental and
physical elements. All that is real is momentary, and either
physical (bhuta) or mental (citta).The object of the world are
a conglomeration of either physical elements or mental
elements or both. No object is permanent or abiding, but
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
896
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
since it is in the form of an incessant series, it gives the
impression of permanence. These objects are directly known
in perceptual cognition. When there is simultaneity of
appearance of the cognizing consciousness. Likewise, a
cognizing consciousness may also exist independently of the
cognized object. In this way, the Vaibhāsika School
advocates dualism in its metaphysics and realism in its
epistemology. The Vaibhāsika School concentrates more on
the analysis of mental phenomena, and we find an elaborate
psychological analysis in the literature belonging to this
school.
Sautrantika School
The Sautrantika School derives its name from a commentary
called Sutranta. It is also a realistic school, sharing its
metaphysics with Vaibhāsikas. Sautrantikas believe in the
momentary existence of the real and classify them into
mental and physical. The mental and the physical are
basically independent of each other, though subsequently
they may interact. Sautrantikas regard the object to exist
independently of the noetic process. The object, the
cognizer, and the cognition are all distinct. The object may
be known or may not be known. If an object is known, it
cannot be known in direct perception. In this respect they
differ from Vaibhāsikas. According to Sautrantikas, the
moment of existence of the object and the moment of the
cognition of the object cannot be the same because cognition
follows and presupposes existence, and every existence
precedes its cognition. There cannot be simultaneity of
existence and its cognition. The sautrantika thinkers examine
and refute the Vaibhāsika position in this respect. In fact,
this is the major point of difference between the two schools.
The Sautrantikas argue that the object of knowledge exists
independently of the cognizing consciousness, and it ceases
to exist in the next moment. So, when it comes into
existence at the very moment, it is not cognized, and it
cannot be cognized. It does not exist in the next moment to
be perceptually cognized, so there is never any perceptual
cognition of an object. However, it does not mean that an
object can never be cognized. There is another mode of
cognizing an object. Before an object ceases to exist, it
leaves out its impression this impression is the exact copy of
its original and has semblance (sārupya) with it. The
cognizing consciousness perceptually apprehends only this
impression, and through this perceptual apprehension of the
impression it infers the original object. Thus, Sautrantikas
introduce the concept of object impression and through this
advocate the representative theory of perception. For them
all cognitions are represented cognition of the object. An
object-Qua-object is not directly perceived. Only its
impression is perceived, and because of the resemblance of
the two and cognitive non-availability of the object the
impression is taken to be the original object.
Mādhyamika School
The third school is Mādhyamika, which is philosophically
very significant. Nāgarjuna has been the first known
exponent of this school. He argues that Buddha's teaching
consisting in the madhyamapratipada(middle path) to be
followed for the realization of nirvāna, which is cessation of
all suffering. According to Nāgarjuna, Buddha advocated
sunya(essencelessness) of all existence. All existence is
sunya(
essenceless
The pluralistic and realistic philosophy of the Sarvāstivāda
culminates in a monistic and idealistic philosophy of
Vijñānavāda (Yogācāra) by way of critique and rejection of
Sunyavāda. The representative theory of perception of the
Sautrantikas implies that all that is cognized is the content of
cognition, and the content of the cognition has a form of its
own, which has sameness of form (sārupya) with the form
of the object. It resulted in the theory of sākārajñānavāda, a
theory according to which every-cognition has a form of its
own apart from the form given to it by its object. From the
theory of sākārajñānavādathere was a natural transition to
the theory that only contents of cognition or vijñānas(ideas)
are real and that they alone are cognized. The external
objects are only hypostatization. They are presumed to be
there, but, in fact, they are only projections of the
consciousness. Consciousness alone is real. Thus, in
Vijñānavāda we find repudiation of the theory that the object
of cognition exists externally and independently of the
cognizing consciousness (bāhyarthavāda). The
consciousness that alone is primarily real is momentary and
is in the form of a continuous flow (pravāha). The
Vijñānavāda advocates three levels of reality, namely,
parikalpita(imaginary), pāratāntrika(dependent or empirical
reality), and pāramārthika (transcendental reality).
Transcendental reality is conceived to be unitary stream of
consciousness, technically known as ālayaVijñāna. It is a
storehouse of consciousness in the sense that it is the
foundation of all streams of consciousness that are
responsible for the appearance of the world of external
objects. It is a repository of the old impressions (samskāras)
and a depository of new impressions. In this way
ālayavijñāna is the only ultimate reality. In itself it is pure
and cannot be characterized. It can be experienced only in
the state of nirvāna. The other level of reality is empirical,
) in the sense that they do not have self-
existence (svabhāva).Every existence has a borrowed
existence or a dependent existence (pratītyasamutpanna);
svabhavasunyata (lack of independent existence)
characterizes all reals. The same position holds good in
respect of all thought and language. Just as all real is self-
negating, all thought and all language are also self- negating,
Nāgarjuna exposes the hollowness and self-contradictory
nature of the important concepts and doctrines prevalent in
his time in Buddhist and non-Buddhist philosophies. He
successfully employs the weapons of sunyata and
pratītyasamutpada to demolish all systems of metaphysics.
He advocates a twofold approach to reality in terms of
samvrutisatya
(empirical real) and
paramārtasatya(transcendental real).Both are characterized
by sånyata in different ways. Empirical is Svabhāvasunya
(devoid of intrinsic existence), and transcendental is
prapañcasunya.Byprapañca he means display of thought and
language. Nāgarjuna emphasizes the anti-metaphysical,
practical, and pragmatic nature of Buddha's teaching and
lays stress on the attainment of prajña(wisdom) leading to
sīla(noble conduct)and samādhi(state of equipoise).This
school is known as Mādhyamika because of its emphasis on
madhyamapratipada, which is a practical middle path,
avoiding all extremes. It is known as Sunyavāda because of
its exposition of essencelessness of all real on account of its
dependent character.
Yogācāra School
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
897
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
which consists of finite stream of consciousness and objects
of consciousness. It is the level of the empirical world that
we experience in our ordinary life. It is a reality that is
amenable to empirical knowledge and linguistic expression.
It is empirical reality (samvrutisatya), as different from
transcendental reality (pāramārthikasatya).
According to those Buddhist sectors Buddhist logic split into
two main schools such as Hīnayāna (Theravada) and
Mahāyāna. Due to the differences of their opinions, the
nyāya of one school is not applicable to the other. In
particular, the Nyāya analyses of such Mahāyānic teachers
as Dinnāga and Dharmakīrti are not relevant to the
Theravāda. Ven.HagodaKhemanandaThera (A Sri Lankan
Buddhist Scholar) has scrutinized the Theravāda Buddhist
Logic in his Great work named “Logic and Epistemology in
Theravāda” [44] Ven.Thero has explained like this: “The
practice of certain scholars to mix all such divergent
Buddhist Nyāya systems is baffling to the average Buddhist
who seeks clear understanding of the matter. Although some
such fundamental principles as the Four Noble Truths are
common to all schools, there is a marked difference in the
analysis of the sources of knowledge between Mahāyāna and
Theravāda. Therefore, it is not appropriate to take what may
be called Buddhist Nyāya as one homogeneous system.
What we would like to stress is that a Nyāya for Theravāda
has to be built solely on the basis of the Pāli Tripitaka”. [45]
There are a sizeable number of Nyāya treatises compiled by
both Mahayana teachers like Nāgarjuna and Hīnayāna
teachers belonging to such schools as Sarvāstivāda. Some
call all such schools, with the exception of Theravāda,
‘Northern Buddhism’ for the reason that they subsequently
existed in Northern India. Equally, the pāli Buddhism which
found a home in Sri Lanka and Southern India is called
‘Southern Buddhism’. Therefore it seems reasonable to call
all forms of Buddhist Nyāya compiled in Sanskrit, whether
they are Hīnayāna or Mahāyāna, ‘Northern Buddhist Nyāya’
and the Nyāya in Pāli which belongs to Southern Buddhism
‘Theravada Nyāya’ or ‘Southern Buddhist Nyāya’. The
Northern Buddhist Nyāya is rich in content. It is believed
that Dinnāga alone compiled more than one hundred Nyāya
treatises.
The Tripitaka which consist of Sutta, Vinaya and
Abhidhamma is the content of Theravada. It has existed in
Sri Lanka for twenty two centuries and Myanmar, Thailand
and Campuchia for fifteen centuries. The learned
Mahātheras (High priests) of these countries have enriched
the Buddhist literature by compiling commentaries, sub-
commentaries and various other exegetical works.
Nevertheless, in this literature as it is at present, we do not
find any work on Logic or Nyāya. Although some tend to
describe Nettippakarana as a TheravādaNyāya work, in
actuality what it contains is only some method of explaining
the doctrine. In other words, this work tells us how a given
statement from the teaching (of the Buddha) may be
explained meaningfully. Petakopadesaclosely follows the
former. In addition, there are Saddasāratthajālini,
Saddattabedhacintā, Ditthantaratanāvali and Nītipadavali
which have been subsequently added to the same line of
thought, but none countable as a Theravada Nyāya work.
There are reasons to believe that the Theravada tradition had
some Nyāya works in the past. The Sri Lankan commentator
Mahānāmathera who wrote during the reign of king
Kumaradāsa,516 A.D., supports his explanation to
suññoloko” in Patisambhidāmagga by referring to a Nyāya
work that presumably existed in his time. [46] A similar
reference to a Nyāya work is available in thavamsa of the
13
th
century. [47] In addition, it must be mentioned that there
are some Nyāya methods scattered in many parts of the
Tripitaka.
The reasons not to develop the Theravāda Buddhist Nyāya
are mentioned By Ven.Khemananda thero as follows:
1) People in those countries were less dogmatic and more
pliable compared to the Brahmins in India. And this may
have contributed to the situation that the Buddhist
teachers did not require logical treatises to convince the
local groups.
2) An ancient tradition of early Buddhism (represented in
Atthaka and Pārāyanavaggās of Suttanipāta) underscore
the view that debate is a result of dogmatism, and that
such exercises would not conduce for emancipation. This
explains why the Theravādins were less enthusiastic
about developing an art of debate.
3) Theravādins were very particular about the pristine purity
of their doctrine, and they made sure that it was not
corrupted by any heretic views. Whenever there was an
attempt to introduce any doctrine, which was against
Theravāda, such an attempt was thwarted at the very
outset. This may have done away with the necessity in
the Theravada tradition of forming any logical treatises.
4) Finally, the Theravādins did not require separate treatises
of logic for the entire Tripitaka was arranged in such a
way that it facilitated the logical understanding of truth.
In particular, the AbhidhammaPitaka reveals the
Theravāda philosophy, and the study of the
Visuddhimagga will give the student the quintessence of
Buddhist logic. [48]
11. Conclusion
The Indian logic covers a period of over two thousand years.
From the time of Mahābhārata, till about the seventeenth
century A.D., when it culminated in a formal discipline of
language in the neo-logical school of Navadeepa in Bengal,
it is spread through three different disciplines, the discipline
of orthodox Hindu logic, the discipline of Buddhist logic and
the discipline of Jain logic.The earliest reference to logic or
science of debate seem to be contained in
chāndogyaupanisadand the Mahābhārata is very important
for the historical development of logic.in Brāhmanic
literature. Dinnāga and Dharmakīrti, Sāntaraksita and
Kamalasīla are eminent Buddhist logicians who have
compiled Buddhist logical rules in order.
Udyotakara,Vātsyāyana, Vācaspati, Udayana and other
Hindu logician have made a theoretical preparations for
Indian logic.
References
[1] Kathavatthu.Siameseedit.quoted by S.C.Vidyābhusaõa
F.234.
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
898
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
[2] Mahābhāratasabhāparva, 5 adhyāya,5.
[3] MahābhārataSāntiparva,adhyāya 180.47-49.
[4] natarkasāstradagdhāyatathaivapisunāyaca”.
ibid.,adhyāya 246, 8.
[5] traividyohetukastarkīnairuktodharapātakah
trayascasraminopurveparisadsyaddasāvarā
.Manusamhitā,Adhyāya 12,111.
[6] yo’vamanyetate mule hetusāstrāsrayāddvijah
sasādhubhirbahiskāryonāstikovedanindakah
.Manusamhitā,adhyāya 2,11.
[7] ārùamdharmopadesamcavedasāsterāvirodhina
yastarkenānusamdhattesadharmamvedanetarāþ” .
Manusamhitā,adhyāya,12,106.
[8] See Vidyābhsana’s History of Indian Logic pp.36-39.
[9] For the roots of the Nyāya-vaisesika doctrines in the
Upanisads,SeeRanade’s “A constructive survey of the
Upanisadic philosophy”,p.190.also compare prof.
S.Radhakrisna`s remarks about Nyāya logic in his
Indian philosophy,vol.1(1923).p.263.
[10] Kathopanisad, 1.2.9.
[11] Which states, that an entity is the negation of its
opposite.
[12] Rhys Davids,Buddhist Psychology.,p.68.
[13] Vide. Barlingay S.S., A modern introduction to Indian
Logic.,p.1.Introduction
[14] Keith A.B.-Buddhist Philosophy. 303.
[15] Rhys Davids C.A.F.-Logic (Buddhist) in Hasitings'
Encyclopedia of Religion and Ethics.p.132.
[16] Chatterji D.C., Buddhist Logic-Article, Annals of the
Bhandarkar Oriental Institute.Vol.34.
[17] Pramāna-Vārtika-Vrutti, 4. Likewise, in his
TarkabhāsaMoksākaragupta holds that in hearing sound
or seeing far away objects like the moon, the validity of
awareness consists in the very experience of the own-
form of the objects irrespective of the actual attainment
of efficient operation pertaining to the object.
[18] In PramānaViniscayaDharmakīrti defines error
(bhrānti)as consisting in grasping that (a real object)in
non-that (an intentional);see katsura-1984.233,n.64.
[19] Cakkhuviññānam _ (ocular consciousness)
Sota ,, - (auditory consciousness)
Ghana ,, - (olfactory consciousness)
Jivhā ,, - (gustatory consciousness)
Kāya ,, - (tactual consciousness) and
Mano ,, - (mental consciousness).
[20]
Gambhīrāduddasāduranubodhāsantāpanitāatakkavacar
ānipunāpanditavedani”-DighaNikāya. 1. 12.
[21] Pāli canon refer to six fold higher knowledge attainable
after the fourth stage of Jhāna (meditation)
viz.1.iddhividha (assuming multiple
forms),2.dibbasotadhātu(clairaudience),3.cetopariyajñan
a(telepathic knowledge),4.pubbe
niwasanussatijñāna(retro cognitive knowledge),5.dibba
cakkhu(clairvoyance) and
6.āsawakkhayajñāna(knowledge of the destruction of
defiling elements).
[22] tamahamjānāmipassāmi "Majjhima
Nikāya,1.329/"jānatā,passatā”M.N.11,111./Nibbāna is
also said to be seen “nibbānampasseyyamti”,M.N.
1.511.
[23] SuttaNipāta furnishes with an inferential method to
show how there can be no caste-distinctions. The trees,
worms, ants, serpents, birds and other creatures possess
characteristics denoting species (“lingam jātimayam”)).
So we find different species among them
(“aññamaññajātiyo”). But among human beings there is
no such characteristics denoting species
(“evamnatthimanussesu lingam Jātimayamputhå”).So it
is concluded that there can be no species or caste among
them(“manussesvetamnavijjati”)SuttaNipata 117-119.
[24] “evam….bhikkhuariyamatthangikammaggambhavento
….nibbānaninnohoti”.Samyukta Nikāya.,v.58
[25] tatrāvusobhikkhunāattanāvāattānamevamanuminitabb
am”-the last word of this line suggests to give the sutta
the title Anumāna to mean 'inferring'. One of the many
references contained in this sutta is ‘the man of evil
inclination is displeasing and disagreeable to me, and of
I incline to evil, others will regard me likewise as
displeasing and disagreeable. Realizing this almsman
must train his heart never to give way to evil
inclination’. AnumānaSutta- MajjhimaNikāya.
[26] The inference here is like - 'if P then Q, not Q therefore
no Q'.
[27] ‘Principles of Gautama’ says Prof. Rhys David, can be
‘found in one or other of the orthodox systems’.-
Buddhism., pp 83-84., ‘Early Buddhism is not an
absolutely original doctrine’-Dr. S. Radhakrisnan-
Indian Philosophy., vol.1.
[28] ññassasamanassavāBrahmanassavāsutvavadāmi,api
cayad eve
mayāsomamñātamsāmamditthamsāmamviditam tat
eva'hamvadāmiti”-SamyuktaNikāya.,v 390.
[29] 1.Anussava-traditional hearings (like
Vedas),2.Paramparā-tradition in general,3.Itikirāya-
report,4.Pitaka sampadā-
scripture in
general,5.Bhavyaråpatā-eminence of the speaker and
6.Samano no garu-prestige of the speaker.
[30] Sussutamtathā-well remembered and true,
Sussutamaññatā-well remembered and false,
Dussutamtathā-ill rememebered and true,
Dussutamaññathā-ill remembered and false-Majjima
Nikāya-1.520.
[31] In Apannakasutta we find the Buddha asking people to
decide their course of life on purely rational grounds, if
they are not in a position to see the objective truth.
Reason thus can act as pointer to the right path.
[32] If water purification can free one of evil karma (A) then
the Fishes, tortoises, frogs etc. will go straight to
heaven,(B)But B is absurd and false so it implies the
absurdity of A.-Therigāthā.,240-1
[33] MajjhimaNikāya,XXVШ.The rationalistic aspect of
Buddha's doctrine finds a brilliant exposition in George
Grimm’s “The doctrine of the Buddha or the religion of
Reason”, Leipzing1926.
[34] tāpācchedāccanikasātsuvarnamivapanditaih
parãksyabhiksavograhyammadvaconatu gauravāt ”.-
Tattvasamgraha,Kārikā,3588.
[35] Rhys Davids C.A.F., Logic
(Buddhist);Hesting’sEncyclopaedia of Religion and
Ethics;Vol.8,132.
[36] Opammavagga contains sections on parables-
kakacupa (discourse on parable of saw)
alagaddupamā (discourses on parable of water snake)
hatthipadopamā (simile of elephant foot print) and
Saropamā (simile of pith).
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
899
International Journal of Science and Research (IJSR)
ISSN (Online): 2319-7064
Index Copernicus Value (2015): 78.96 | Impact Factor (2015): 6.391
Volume 6 Issue 1, January 2017
www.ijsr.net
Licensed Under Creative Commons Attribution CC BY
[37] Law B.C-History of Pāli literature-p.646.
[38] MilindaPañha was probably composed in 100 A.D.
There are many controversies regarding its exact date.
[39] vibhajjavādo…aham-MajjhimaNikāya 1.197.
[40] ekamsikapi……mayādhammādesitapaññattā”-Dīgha
Nikāya.1.191.
[41] "ekamsavacanamekamvibhajjavacanamparamtatiyampa
tipuccheyyacatutthamthāpaye”-Anguttara Nikāya.1.197.
[42] "ekamsenavibhāgenaprechatahsthāpanīyatahvyakrutam
maranotpattivisistātmānyatādivat”–AbhidharmaKosa.
v.22.
[43] Sassatoloko-The world is eternal,Assassatoloko-The
world is not eternal,Antavaloko-The world is finite,
Anantavaloko-The world is infinite, Tam jīvam tam
sarīram-The Soul is identical with the
body,Aññamjīvamaññamsarīram-The soul is different
the body,Hotitathāgatoparammarana-The tathāgata
exists after death,Nahotitathāgatoparammaranā-The
tathāgata does not exist after
death,Hoticanahoticatathāgatoparammaranā-The
tathāgata exists and does not exist after
death,Nevahotinahotitathāgatoparammaranā-The
tathāgata neither exist nor does not exist after death.
[44] Khemananda H.Ven.;Logic and Epistemology in
Theravāda(TheravādaNyāya),Translated from Sinhala
by:AsangaTilakaratne,Karunaratna and Sons
Ltd,1993.(Available in Buddhist Cultural Center,
Dehiwala-Sri Lanka.
[45] Ibid, p.2
[46] Tathanāyaganthecasaddaganthecaayamevaattho”.
(paµisambhida aµµhakatha,Hevavitarana
Edition.p.358.)
[47] Santappayamdhammasudharasena-
Yomānusetundilasukaropi
Isīvakatvāathanāyaganthamnijampavattesicirāyadham
mam” ( thavamsa,41.)
[48] KhemanandaH.Ven.; Logic and Epistemology in
Theravada,pp.4-5.
Paper ID: ART20163177
DOI: 10.21275/ART20163177
900